Utility Theory Under Uncertainty

Introduction

In a single period model, agents must decide today how much to consume and how much to save for later. In this note we take that decision as given, and assume that agents derive their utility from consumption at the end of the period. As is common in finance, consumption is represented by a single good. Agents prefer more to less, but the marginal utility of each additional unit of consumption is decreasing, i.e., the last bite is never as good as the first one.

We capture this intuition by a utility function \(u: \mathbb{R}^{+} \rightarrow \mathbb{R}.\) The domain of the utility function is real consumption and therefore cannot be negative. In the following, we assume that \(u(c)\) is continuous and differentiable of all orders. The level of utility is not important, and can even be negative, but we assume that the utility function is increasing and strictly concave.1 Mathematically, it must be the case that \(u'(c) > 0\) and \(u''(c) < 0.\) In some cases it will also be useful to consider utility functions such that \(u'(0) = \infty\), that is, in starvation an extra unit of consumption provides an infinite amount of extra utility.

1 A function \(f: D \rightarrow \mathbb{R}\) is concave if \[ f(t x_{1} + (1 - t) x_{2}) \geq t f(x_{1}) + (1 - t) f(x_{2}) \] for all \(x_{1}, x_{2} \in X\) and \(0 \leq t \leq 1.\) The function is strictly concave if the inequality is strict.

2 Remember that \[ y^{x} = \exp(x \ln(y)) \approx 1 + x \ln(y) \] for small x.

A common choice of utility function is \[ u(c) = \dfrac{c^{1 - \gamma} - 1}{1 - \gamma}, \] where \(\gamma \geq 0.\) A special case occurs when \(\gamma = 1,\) since2 \[ \lim_{\gamma \rightarrow 1} \frac{c^{1 - \gamma} - 1}{1 - \gamma} = \lim_{\gamma \rightarrow 1} \frac{1 + (1 - \gamma) \ln(c) - 1}{1 - \gamma} = \ln(c). \]

This function is called power utility if \(\gamma \neq 1\) and log utility if \(\gamma = 1\).3 The marginal utility in this case is given by \(u'(c) = c^{-\gamma}.\)

3 Many textbooks and programming use \(\log\) instead of \(\ln.\) In this notes I will use \(\ln\) to denote the natural logarithm.

Another common utility function is \[ u(c) = - e^{-a c}, \] called the exponential utility function. We will see that both types of utility functions induce different attitudes under uncertainty.

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

The analysis in the next two sections closely follows Chapter 1 in Ingersoll (1987). Denote by \(W\) the wealth of the agent at the end of the period. This wealth is generated by investing a certain amount today. In general, \(W\) is unkown today and can be thought as a random variable defined over a probability space \((\Omega, \prob).\)

Ingersoll, Jonathan E. 1987. Theory of Financial Decision Making. Vol. 3. Rowman & Littlefield.

When faced with uncertainty, the utility of final consumption is also random. Thus, the agent is not so much worried about the level of consumption as she is about the utility she might get from that level of consumption. We can model the agent’s behavior using the concept of expected utility. The utility derived by a random consumption \(\overset{\sim}{W}\) is given by \[ U(\wtilde{W}) = \ev(u(\wtilde{W})). \] Thus, we have that \(\wtilde{W}_{1} \succsim \wtilde{W}_{2}\) if \(U(\wtilde{W}_{1}) \geq U(\wtilde{W}_{2}),\) and \(\wtilde{W}_{1} \sim \wtilde{W}_{2}\) if \(U(\wtilde{W}_{1}) = U(\wtilde{W}_{2}).\) Note that the expected utility of a certain level of wealth \(W\) is just \(u(W).\)

Consider now a random variable \(\tilde{\varepsilon}\) such that \(\ev(\tilde{\varepsilon}) = 0\) and \(\var(\tilde{\varepsilon}) > 0.\) We say that an agent is risk-averse if she prefers a certain level of wealth \(W\) over a random payoff with the same expected value. If we define \(\wtilde{W} = W + \tilde{\varepsilon}\), we have that \(\ev(\wtilde{W}) = W,\) but \(\var(\wtilde{W}) > 0 = \var(W).\) Thus, the agent is risk-averse if \[ u(W) > \ev(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon})). \tag{1}\] In order to understand better the notion of risk-aversion, we will use the following result.

Property 1 (Jensen’s Inequality) Let \(f: D \rightarrow \mathbb{R}\) be a twice-continuously differentiable and strictly concave function, and \(X\) a random variable defined in a probability space \((\Omega, \prob)\) such that the range of \(X\) is contained in the domain of \(f,\) and \(\var(X) > 0.\) Then we have that \[ f(\ev(X)) > \ev(f(X)). \]

Proof Let \(m = \ev(X).\) The second-order Taylor expansion of \(f\) around \(m\) is \[ f(x) = f(m) + f'(m)(x - m) + \frac{1}{2} f''(\xi_{L}) (x - m)^{2}, \] where \(\xi_{L}\) is between \(m\) and \(x.\) Let \(x = X\) and take expectations to find \[ \ev(f(X)) = f(\ev(X)) + \frac{1}{2} f''(\xi_{L}) \var(X) < f(\ev(X)), \] since \(f''(\xi_{L}) < 0\) and \(\var(X) > 0.\)

Jensen’s inequality shows that strict concavity in \(u\) implies risk-aversion. The converse is also true. Consider a risk-averse investor with utility function \(u\) and a gamble \(\tilde{\varepsilon}\) that pays \((1 - q) a\) with probability \(q\) and \(-q a\) with probability \(1 - q.\) The gamble is fair since \[ \ev(\tilde{\varepsilon}) = q (1 - q) a - (1 - q) q a = 0. \] A risk-averse investor, though, dislikes the gamble implying \[ u(W) > \ev(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon})) = q u(W + (1 - q)a) + (1 - q) u(W - q a). \tag{2}\] Because \(W = q W + (1 - q)a + (1 - q) (W - q a)\) for all values of \(a\) and \(q\) such that \(W + (1 - q)a\) and \(W - q a\) are in the domain of \(u,\) equation (Eq. 2) implies that \(u\) is strictly concave.

Property 2 (Risk Aversion and Concavity of the Utility Function) An agent is risk averse as defined in (Eq. 1) if and only if her utility function is strictly concave.

In many situations, we are forced to take on a risky gamble. For example, if you buy a car you face the risk of an accident that can induce in costly repairs. Many people chose to pay for insurance and hence reduce the risk of the car. In our framework, we define the insurance premium as the maximum amount that an agent is willing to pay to eliminate the risk.

To formalize this notion, consider an asset with value \(W.\) After you buy the asset, you can either face the risk of owning the asset producing a wealth of \(W + \tilde{\varepsilon},\) or pay \(\Pi_{i}\) to insure the asset, which guarantees a certain wealth of \(W - \Pi_{i}.\) An agent is indifferent between the two choices if \[ u(W - \Pi_{i}) = \ev(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon})). \tag{3}\] The value of \(\Pi_{i}\) that solves (Eq. 3) is called the insurance premium. We comparing two agents attitudes towards risk, the agent who is willing to pay the most for insurance is more risk averse than the other.

In the previous analysis, since the agent is indiferent between the risky gamble and getting \(W - \Pi_{i},\) we call this difference the certainty equivalent.

Example 1 Suppose the economy can be in one of the following two states: (i) Boom or “good” state and (ii) Recession or “bad” state, which can occur with equal probability. Consider a risky asset that would have a price of $50 in the good state and $10 in the bad state, which currently trades at $30. Two investors are evaluating this asset.

The utility function of the first investor (A) is \[ u(W)=10 \ln(W), \] whereas for the second investor (B) we have \[ u(W) = 2W + 5. \]

What is the maximum price that investors A and B would be willing to pay for the risky asset?

The expected utility of the risky asset for investor A is \[ E(U) = 0.5 (10 \ln(10)) + 0.5(10 \ln(50)) = 31.0730. \] Therefore, the maximum price that the agent is willing to pay for the asset is its certainty equivalent (\(CE\)), i.e., \[ \begin{aligned} 10 \ln(CE) & =31.0730 \\ \ln(CE) & = 3.1073 \\ CE & = \exp(3.1073) = \$22.36. \end{aligned} \]

For investor B, the expected utility of the risky asset is \[ E(U) = 0.5 (2 \times 10 + 5) + 0.5 (2 \times 50 + 5) = 65. \] The maximum price that the agent is willing to pay for the asset is its certainty equivalent: \[ \begin{aligned} 2 \times CE + 5 & = 65 \\ 2 \times CE & = 60 \\ CE & = \$30. \end{aligned} \]

Local Risk Aversion

Intuitively, a function that is more concave should induce more risk aversion than a function that is less concave. We can formalize this intuition by looking at the insurance premium for a gamble with a very small variance.

Let \(\ev(\tilde{\varepsilon}) = 0\) and \(\var(\tilde{\varepsilon}) > 0\). We know that the insurance premium \(\Pi_{i}\) solves \(u(W - \Pi_{i}) = \ev(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon}))\).

First, do a Taylor expansion of first order of \(u(W - \Pi_{i})\) around \(W\): \[ \begin{aligned} u(W - \Pi_{i}) & \approx u(W) + u'(W) (W - \Pi_{i} - W) \\ & = u(W) - u'(W) \Pi_{i}. \end{aligned} \tag{4}\] Second, do a Taylor expansion of second order of \(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon})\) around \(W\): \[ \begin{aligned} u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon}) & \approx u(W) + u'(W) (W + \tilde{\varepsilon} - W) + \frac{1}{2} u''(W) (W + \tilde{\varepsilon} - W)^{2} \\ & = u(W) + u'(W) \tilde{\varepsilon} + \frac{1}{2} u''(W) \tilde{\varepsilon}^{2} \\ \ev(u(W + \tilde{\varepsilon})) & \approx u(W) + \frac{1}{2} u''(W) \sigma^{2}_{\varepsilon}. \end{aligned} \tag{5}\]

Equating (Eq. 4) and (Eq. 5) we find that: \[ \Pi_{i} \approx -\frac{1}{2} \frac{u''(W)}{u'(W)} \sigma_{\varepsilon}^{2}. \tag{6}\] The previous expression shows that for a initial wealth of \(W,\) the insurance premium depends positively on the local curvature of the utility function at that point as measured by \(-u''(W).\)

We denote by \[ \mathit{ARA} = - \frac{u''(W)}{u'(W)} \] the coefficient of absolute risk-aversion, and by \[ \mathit{RRA} = - \frac{u''(W)}{u'(W)} W \] the coefficient of relative risk-aversion.

Example 2 Take \[ u(C) = \frac{C^{1 - \gamma} - 1}{1 - \gamma} \] Then \(u'(C) = C^{-\gamma}\) and \(u''(C) = -\gamma C^{-\gamma - 1}\), implying that \[ RRA = -\left( \frac{-\gamma W^{-\gamma -1}}{W^{-\gamma}}\right) W = \gamma \] Power utility is an example of a function that exhibits constant relative risk-aversion.